Thursday, September 16, 2010

Alone in the Universe

My argument for the existence of some sort of Creator God is that we seem to be alone in the universe.

Science has peered outward and found that there are as many as 200 billion galaxies in the observable universe. There are some 100 billion stars in our own galaxy, the Milky Way. Our own star, the sun, is very, very average in size and age, and exists in the humdrum outer reaches of a plain-vanilla spiral galaxy. Yet it has just one inhabited planet, as far as we know: earth.

We have lately discovered planets around other stars in the galaxy, though we can't as yet detect any planets as small as ours. So we have not yet confirmed the existence of planets elsewhere whose conditions can be considred ripe for the evolution of life. I assume, however, that innumerable such planets exist, and the question is, are any of them inhabited by intelligent life forms?

In his Cosmos TV series and book, the late astronomer Carl Sagan presented the Drake equation giving an estimate of the potential number of extraterrestrial civilizations in the Milky Way galaxy. Frank Drake, an American astronomer and astrophysicist, devised the equation to take into account:

  • the average yearly rate of star formation in the galaxy
  • the fraction of those stars that have planets
  • the average number of planets per star that can potentially support life
  • the fraction that actually develop life at some point
  • the fraction of life-bearing planets that develop intelligent life, and therefore civilizations
  • the fraction of civilizations that develop a technology that gives off detectable signs of their existence into space
  • the length of time such civilizations give off detectable signals into space (as they may cease doing so for a number of reasons, including self-destruction via, say, nuclear weapons)

These imprecise factors were estimated by Drake in such a way as to yield a result of just 10 civilizations in our galaxy with which communication might be possible.

Of course, if there are 200 billion galaxies out there, by such estimates there may be on the order of 10 x 200 billion, or 2,000 billion planets in the cosmos that can give off signs of intelligent life. In SETI, the Search for Extra-Terrestrial Intelligence, we have been searching for such signs for the last fifty years. So far, nothing.

Meanwhile, Sagan in his Cosmos series was openly skeptical about such things as UFOs and alien abductions. There is no hard evidence, he said, that any earthling has ever encountered beings from outer space.

My guess, in view of all the above, is that we're alone. If I'm right, then what does that say to us?

I personally believe in evolution. Life somehow began on earth and then evolved, producing (among countless other species) us. No one in the scientific community knows for sure how life began on earth. Darwin himself simply assumed that it began in ways that lie outside the scope of his theory of evolution.

Logically, if life began in the same way on Planet X, a planet enough like ours to allow intelligent life to evolve in the ordinary way, then there must be some non-zero probability, however tiny, that intelligent life would evolve on that Planet X. The "however tiny" probability factor here relates closely to Drake's fraction of life-bearing planets that develop intelligent life, and therefore civilizations.

So, if there are really 10 planets in the galaxy that have undergone earth-like evolution leading to currently existing species whose individual members possess minds, then on each of those 10 planets there must have been Darwinian evolution by natural selection from simple, original life forms that lack minds.

Yet we have yet to see any signs whatsoever of "little green men". Where are they?

If they are nowhere, then intelligent life has developed, from an original life form we cannot as yet explain, on earth alone. How decidely odd. Sagan and other scientists have emphasized how ordinary our planet, sun, solar system, and galaxy are. If that's right, then our being absolutely alone (if we indeed are) must mean sommething.

To me, it means there is a Creator God. This God, whatever else is true about Him, Her, or It, must be capable of mighty works: the creation of life. Moreover, He/She/It must be capable of intentionally deciding to create life in just one of numberless hospitable habitats in the physical universe.

We generally say that any being capable of having and expressing such discrimination of intent is a "person" with a "will". So the fact that we are alone implies, to me, a mighty Creator God who is a person with a will. I'll call that person male by convention and use the masculine pronoun accordingly.

If there were more than one such creative Deity, then we would expect more than one instance of intelligent life in the universe. Hence, our Creator God is most likely also alone.

All this says nothing whatever about how the universe itself came to be. It might have existed always and forever. It might have come to be as the result of a big bang, which may or may not imply divine agency, depending on who you ask. My argument sidesteps that discussion entirely. All I'm saying is that, if we're alone in an otherwise vast and fecund universe whose laws are wholly consistent with the sustenance of life and the evolution of intelligence, then maybe that's because the spark of life on our planet came from a God whose intent was to make us His unique creatures.

Saturday, August 14, 2010

Decoding Quantum Reality

A new book by physicist Vlatko Vedral, Decoding Reality: The Universe as Quantum Information, gives me new insights about reality.

We know the world — or, put more expansively, the universe — is made up of matter. Einstein's E=mc2 showed that matter is a form of energy, so matter and energy are the same thing.

Meanwhile, other physicists such as Niels Bohr were showing that the basic particles of matter and energy — say, electrons for matter, photons for energy — behave in ways that defy common sense. Thus was born the science of quantum physics.

Quantum physics — a.k.a. quantum mechanics — shows how the tiny particles and packets of energy that make up everything we know do strange tricks like being in two places at once. You can pass a photon of light through a "beam splitter" and find that half the time it actually does pass straight through, and half the time it gets reflected onto a different path. Which path it takes is truly random.

Actually, it takes both paths at the same time. Only when we measure or observe the photon's behavior do we lock it into once choice or the other.

Before that observation takes place, you could say (but only very, very loosely) that there are two-photons-in-one. Better put, "they" share "mutual information," which means that our observation of "their" behavior at the beam splitter results in that behavior becoming either-or, not both-and, and it only thus becomes consistent with our common sense and logic. (But which choice the observed photon actually uses is a coin flip. We can never, under any circumstances, predict it. We can never force one outcome to occur over the other.)

Mutual information is known to us in our everyday lives. For instance, if two people are in a bar deciding on what drink to order, and if one says to the other, "I'll have what you're having," then an observer would say there exists mutual information. Knowing what Imbiber A orders tells us what Imbiber B is going to have.

Vlatko Vedral talks a lot about mutual information, which is what typically occurs in the world of "quantum information."

Quantum information is an enlargement of "information theory." The latter began in the middle of the 20th century when Bell Labs researcher Claude Shannon was trying to figure out how best to send information down a noisy telephone line. What is information, actually? asked Shannon. It's anything that, by surprising us in some way, conveys a state of affairs we weren't expecting. "Congratulations, you've won the lottery!" contains a huge amount of information. Static on a telephone line contains zero information (especially in the old, pre-digital days when static was always present on phone lines).

We know that information is, on a computer, contained in bits. Each bit is either a zero or a one. In quantum information, quantum bits or "qubits" are used instead of regular bits. A qubit can in effect be zero and one at the same time. For example, it can be "1/3 zero" and "2/3 one." That is, when we actually observe it and lock it into one definite value or the other, 0 or 1, the chance that it will wind up being zero is 1-in-3, while the chance that it will wind up being one is 2-in-3.

As long as the probability that it's zero and the probability that it's one — after being observed by us, that is — no laws of nature are being violated at all.

So what? Well, the answer to that question has practical dimensions and philosophical ones. I'll let Mr. Vedral tell you about some of the practical ones in his video discussion of his book:




The philosophical dimensions are the ones that interest me. Vedral hints at some of them toward the end of his video.

He shows, mainly in the last part of his book, that there's good reason to believe that information — of the quantum variety — is the stuff of all reality. Matter and energy very likely emerge from qubits, and qubits are repositories of mutual information which — only when they are measured by some observer such as us, using a beam splitter — behave themselves like regular bits, 0's or 1's, of information.

But where do the qubits come from? Here's where things get very interesting. Quantum information doesn't have to have a source or cause of existence.

If we ignore for a moment that qubits are probabilistic and think of them as if they were regular bits, we know that regular bits represent numbers (out of which computers construct other sorts of data). Numbers can, like qubits, be said to be primary to all our reality. That's why quantum theory and Einstein's theory of relativity can be collapsed into a set of formulas like E=mc2. Formulas are just ways of manipulating numbers.

So to answer the question of where do number-representing qubits come from, we can ask where numbers themselves come from. Vedral shows (borrowing from computer pioneer John von Neumann) that numbers come from ... nothing whatsoever!

The behavior of numbers can be shown to depend on "set theory." "Sets" are, basically, collections of numbers. {1,2} is a set of numbers that is, in turn, a subset of {1,2,3}. {1} is a subset of {1,2}. Does {1} have any subset? Yes: the "empty" set.

Von Neumann showed that the empty set contains itself ... meaning that the contained empty set has one element. Thus does the number 1 emerge from the number 0!

The contained empty set also contains itself. Thus does the number 2 emerge from the number 1!

And so on. All the numbers that exist emerge from an empty set that represents 0, or nothingness!

If qubits equate to numbers, then all quantum information emerges from nothingness. If all the world's a body of quantum information, then the whole universe emerges from (as I'll call it) "zerohood."

Furthermore, each number in the sequence of emergence-from-zerohood depends on all the earlier numbers in the sequence. They share mutual information, just as Imbiber B who says "I'll have what you're having" depends on Imbiber A.

Our act of measurement or observation of quantum behavior is like when we take a photo of kids jumping on a trampoline:



It looks like they're motionless, but of course they're not! Likewise, when we "capture" a quantum event by observing it, it turns into a randomly chosen, but definite, outcome. We lose, meanwhile, the "mutual" information whenever a qubit of information is turned by our observing it into a hard-and-fast bit.

For example, when we observe the position of an electron, we thereby lose any ability to learn its speed, direction of motion, and momentum. An electron's position and its velocity are related by virtue of being mutual information.

Can you tell, in the photo above, whether the kids are on the way up or on the way down?

We could say that the kids' direction is basically, as far as we are concened, a coin flip: we might as well flip an ordinary coin to decide which direction they are going in.

But at the same time, we are aware that what direction the kids were actually going in when the photo was taken is deterministic, not random. If we knew what forces were acting on them just prior to the taking of the photo, we could say for sure what direction they were moving in.

Not so with quantum behavior. There is no way to be sure, for example, which direction of motion a beam splitter will yield when a photon is sent into it: will it pass straight through, or will it be reflected?

Yet, says Vedral, quantum behavior is (according to the equations of quantum theory) just as deterministic as the mechanics of jumping on a trampoline! It's just our act of observing quantum behavior that turns it — seemingly — random.

So there's a mysterious interplay between deterministic quantum information and any and all acts of observation and measurement of that information, which makes the quantum information seem, in some of its aspects, random.

From the point of view of its randomness, quantum information is truly random. It's not like a physical coin flip, which seems random in its result but is actually subject to the laws of classical physics, à la Isaac Newton. If we had enough information about (among other things) the force applied to it by a thumbnail when it is flipped into the air, we would be able to predict with perfect accuracy whether it is going to come down heads or tails.

Not so with "quantum coin flips." No amount of prior knowloedge could tell us whether a photon will pass through a beam splitter or be reflected.

That means that we have no business saying that the outcome of a "quantum coin flip" has a cause! In fact, it has no cause whatsoever.

But everything we observe in the universe is, ultimately, a series of quantum coin flips!

That suggests that the observable universe is, at base, uncaused. As it emerges from "zerohood," it is fundamentally without cause.

This is what really interests me.

We see a world in which, for most practical purposes, everything that happens — every "event" — has a cause. Newton's laws of mechanics and of gravity seem to tell us everything we need to know ...

... except that they don't. Einstein proved that, and then the theorists of quantum physics came along and confounded even Einstein, who said "God does not play dice with the universe."

Well, if there is a God, He clearly does play dice — specifically, the fact is that quantum coin flips are behind everything we see. Before there is matter and energy, the stuff of reality is quantum information.

To me that suggests that we, as observable beings of and in the universe, are radically free. At root we are, by the ceaseless acts of observation that ascertain our very being, a coterie of random, quantum coin flips. At root, we are uncaused.

By the logic that applies to quantum phenomena — see above — we are also, in addition to being random and uncaused, deterministic in the very fabric of our being. We are both random and deterministic. We have free will, by virtue of our essential "quantumness," but we are also swept along in the Newtonian, deterministic flow of all the physical events in the universe.

Wrap your mind around that, if you can!

* * *

This view of reality both giveth and taketh away.

It giveth us the ability to say something intelligent in favor of the gut feeling we all have of possessing free will. Philosophers have long debated free will vs. determinism as if the two were mutually exclusive — as our ordinary, everyday logic would seem to dictate. But if Vedral is right about reality being at base quantum, then ordinary logic need not apply.

We can be wholly deterministic beings like the planets in their orbits, and yet we can still have free will!

Of course, common sense still tells us that that conclusion has to be bogus. Seemingly, we have to be, at base, either free-willed or deterministic. Yet Vedral's worldview says no.

There's still a fundamental mystery here, of course. But there's just as much mystery about all things quantum. Richard Feynman, winner of the 1965 Nobel Prize in Physics, once said, "I think I can safely say that nobody understands quantum mechanics."

This view of reality also taketh away — see above — our justification for imagining that the universe and all things in it have a cause.

We who believe in God are accustomed to thinking that it must be true that, however metaphorical we may take chapter one of the biblical Book of Genesis to be, God caused the universe to come into existence. The view of reality expounded in Vedral's book says no to that.

If we want to trace reality back to God, says Vedral, we must instead do so apophatically. Wikipedia says in this article:
Apophatic theology — also known as Negative theology or Via Negativa (Latin for "Negative Way") — is a theology that attempts to describe God, the Divine Good, by negation, to speak only in terms of what may not be said about the perfect goodness that is God.
For example:
... one should not say that God is wise since that word arrogantly implies we know what "wisdom" means on a divine scale, whereas we only know what wisdom is believed to mean in a confined cultural context.
One can accordingly say only that God is not ignorant.

Similarly odd to our way of thinking is the idea that God does not cause the universe to exist. Yet such apophatic thinking is precisely what gives us any basis at all for claiming free will! If God causes the universe to exist, then there is no entry point for "zerohood." If there is no entry point for zerohood, Vedral's whole view of reality collapses — as does any quantum basis for claiming free will.

That there is, at the most fundamental level, a break in the chain of causation where "zerohood" asserts itself is, to me, a hugely liberating realization. God tolerates a break in the (ordinarily) totally caused chain of events. God, in fact, insists on it!

* * *

Here's what it's like, for me. Unconsciously for the most part, I seem to operate, usually, under the assumption that I am like a driver on a highway who needs, first and foremost, to be a "good citizen of the road" — for, if I'm not, some sort of huge "accident" is bound to happen to an untold number of cars.

My assumption, deep down, usually is that everything is chained inexorably to everything — as would be the case if all the cars on the road were somehow chained to one another, so that if I run amuck, gun my engine, and run myself into a brick wall, they'll all crash too.

But, no. The world is not cars that by "tight causality" are chained inexorably to one another, such that my errors of comission, or merely of omission, will cause untold driver deaths. Rather, the world is — fundamentally is — a set of bumper cars in an amusement park ride.

Ever ride bumper cars? They have a mind of their own. Try as you might to steer them the way you intend, they insist on veering off on their own tangent and hitting — or missing — whatever might come in their way.

If Vedral's view of reality is right, we live in a "bumper cars world." There is so much stuff that happens that is without any cause whatever, that wrecks on the highway are inevitable. They can't be headed off by everyone being "good citizens of the road." They just can't. They're built into the fabric of reality.

Let me try to put it in a more concrete way. In my usual, tightly causal view of reality, I normally am burdened with the assumption that "bad" stuff like, say, homosexuality can be "fought against" successfully. Hence, someone who is homosexual obviously is or has been the victim of something or someone whose influence, way back during the person's formative years, possibly, has "made" that person what he or she is today.

What was it that did that terrible thing, that had that awful influence over the fate of a fellow human being? Possibly it was a gay teacher in elementary school. Possibly it was a character on a kids' TV show. Who knows exactly what it was? But in a tightly causal view of reality, it is something that can be identified, fought against, and rooted out.

By the same token, in a tightly causal view of reality, I personally have a responsibility to do whatever is necessary, on my little part, to help wage a war against all sorts of "bad" stuff like homosexuality. I ought accordingly to support, say, counseling programs that (claim to) turn gays into straights, or ballot initiatives that (hope to) make gay marriage illegal, or campaigns to put the kibosh on, for example, TV Teletubbies who are "obviously gay."

But in a "bumper cars" view of reality, nothing "causes" all the "bad stuff" in the world. Cars just veer into one another, willy-nilly, and I'm personally off the hook if "bad stuff" like homosexuality happens in this, our mutual "society of the road," while I'm behind the wheel of a vehicle.

In fact, "bad stuff," like someone being attracted sexually to his or her own gender, is not put in train by any event, past or present, which has "made" him or her gay. The bumper sticker is right: it is really true — basically, fundamentally — that "shit happens." There is no devil luring us inexorably, by some tightly coupled chain of adverse causality, to wrack and ruin.

If I thereby let the world off the hook for all the wrecks that I personally think I see on the highway — gay sexual orientation being a metaphorical stand-in here for a whole lot of stuff I normally try to steer my own personal bumper car away from, in hopes of making this a "better world" — then I have to let myself off the hook, too. I am in no way responsible for all the shit that happens in the world.

That's why it is a hugely liberating realization that Vedral's book makes me aware of: the fact that there is, at the bottommost level of that-which-is, a fundamental break in the chain of stuff-causing-other-stuff. There is, in the way that I put it earlier, a place at the very bottom of the deck of reality where causal "zerohood" asserts itself, and cards, good or bad, can be dealt completely at random.

That fact alone lets me personally off the hook for all the shit that happens in the world. And then that hugely liberating fact goes on to pay wonderful dividends: it lets me treat myself and everyone else not as bundles of effects of inexorable causes that make us "bad" or "good" without recourse, but as persons who are worthy of respect regardless.

Thursday, May 27, 2010

In Search of (Christian) Charity

I've renamed this blog yet again!

It is now "In Search of Charity." Before, I called it "In Search of Chastity." It turns out that chastity, for me, is elusive.

So is charity, for that matter.

A subjective experience will illustrate. Before describing it, I need to mention that I have a sexual kink. I've always had it. It's — how shall I put it — that, if I dared, I could get many jollies from voyeuristically watching (for instance) what carousing college-age women who've tanked up on beer on a Saturday night are apt to resort to, after the bars close, to restore themselves to comfort behind a parked car in a parking garage.

Get it? Enough said ...

Not daring to do it up close and personal, I seek out porn on the Internet that relates to the bodily function in question. (There's a huge amount of it.)

Now, that's not the only turn-on in my life, but it's the kinkiest. It's so kinky that it makes, for example, being gay "normal" by comparison.

And it's not "chaste": not the urge itself, not the way I satisfy that urge.

But for many years now I have made it my business to try to become more perfect, chastity-wise and with respect to all the other Christian virtues. I was "in search of chastity."

Just recently, after an episode of breaking down and satisfying (online) my kinkiest lechery, I was driving along one afternoon in my car and musing that I was not by any means the unhappy wretch I "ought" to have been for wallowing in such unholy, forbidden stuff.

And it hit me that doing that kind of thing makes me, in a way, more of a Christian. It leads me to charity.

In Christian theology, charity or love means an unlimited loving-kindness toward all others. My reasoning went this way:

I'm not gay — and I don't care about the bodily function I mentioned when it's done by men — but I do have a sexual predilection that, were it to be more common that it is, and were I really to come "out of the closet" about it, would very likely make me just as much of a pariah as being homosexual used to make people, until very recently.

In fact, I'm not at all sure that being lesbian, gay, bisexual, or transgendered today is all that much more accepted than it used to be, underneath today's veneer of political correctness ... but, never mind. The point is that being "different" sexually myself makes me feel more charitable toward those who are also different, but in a different way.

That is, it makes me feel more charitable when I'm not focusing on how chaste I think I (and everybody else) ought to be.

When I'm not into chastity but into charity, as I am at this present moment, there floods over me a feeling of unity with all those other "sinners" that the world is full of — i.e., everybody. For everyone has a "kink" or two in their makeup. It may not be a sexual kink. It may be a sexual predilection that is not usually thought of as "kinky," or it may be something that has nothing to do with sex — if indeed there is anything that has nothing whatever to do with sex. But everyone has something to hide, something they may struggle with and a lot of the time fight a losing battle with.

Then I wondered, after reasoning that far, whether Christianity hasn't put way too many eggs in the basket of chastity, and way too few in the basket of charity.

Didn't Jesus dine with tax collectors, beggars, the diseased, and various persons of questionable social standing who, by the reckoning of the religious leaders of the time and place, were of low station for the very reason that they were unclean sinners, and the Lord God was punishing them?

Didn't Jesus forgive the prostitute who, according to the religious laws of the day, was being stoned to death?

Those are some of the thoughts I had as I was tooling along in my automobile. They're by no means original thoughts with me. Lots of people have tried to use such notions as a basis for a radically pro-charity theological standpoint. Well and good — but what I really think is that Jesus would have turned up his nose at the theology and urged the unity that charity fosters as a thing in itself.

Friday, March 05, 2010

Abortion Funding and the Health-Care Debate

Federal funding of abortion is front-and-center in the debate over health-insurance reform again. President Obama has proposed that the already passed Senate version of the proposed legislation be passed by the House of Representatives, and Democratic leaders in Congress have concurred. Though the House had already passed its own version of the bill, the bill that passed the Senate last Christmas Eve by a vote of 60-39 is has different provisions.

Ordinarily, a House-Senate conference committee would iron out the differences, and the resulting compromise would hopefully be confirmed by an additional vote each chamber. However, since the Senate passed its bill, a special election in Massachusetts has — ironically, since the Lion of the Senate was a prime mover in health reform — turned the Senate seat formerly held by the late Democrat Edward Kennedy over to Republican Scott Brown. Any bill reported out of a hypothetical House-Senate conference committee would be unlikely to garner the 60 votes it needs in the Senate to break a GOP filibuster and go to the president for his signature.

According to the Democrats' strategy, the problem of needing 60 votes to overcome a GOP filibuster in the Senate can be gotten around by resorting to a procedure called "reconciliation." Intended to be used only for measures such as tax hikes that affect the federal budget, reconciliation bypasses filibusters by needing only a simple majority of 51 senators to pass a bill. So, if the House sets aside its own bill and passes the Senate bill, then (since that bill has already passed the Senate) the House and Senate could in theory pass just the changes proposed by the president. Each chamber would require yea votes by a simple majority of its members to do so. In the Senate, a simple majority of 51 votes would do. Those changes, accordingly, would constitute a separate reconciliation measure or "fixer" bill to be voted on in both the House and the Senate and would appear on the president's desk alongside the Senate bill as passed by the House in place of its own bill.

Ordinarily, the matters taken up by the Senate in any reconciliation measure would have to be restricted to budgetary matters, in order for reconciliation rules to apply.

Hence, reconciliation can be used at all only if one of two things happens. One is that Alan Frumin, the Senate parliamentarian — part of whose duty it is to filter out non-budgetary matters in reconciliation bills — lets all of the changes included in the "fixer" bill come to the Senate floor under the aegis of reconciliation. Or, two, if the parliamentarian balks at that, Vice President Joe Biden has the authority as president of the Senate to overrule Frumin and let the "fixer" bill come up for a vote.

The hitch is this: The Senate bill which the House must now pass according to this strategy contains language concerning the federal funding of abortions that varies from the House version as currently passed. Were the matter to be handled in the usual way, a House-Senate conference committee would need to choose between the more strongly anti-abortion Stupak-Pitts Amendment of the House bill and the weaker language introduced by Senate Majority Leader Harry Reid into the Senate bill.
The reconciliation measure would leave the Senate language unchanged. Stupak-Pitts, in short, would vanish under reconciliation.

Stupak-Pitts, introduced into the House bill by Democratic Rep. Bart Stupak of Michigan and Republican Rep. Joseph R. Pitts of Pennsylvania, prohibits use of federal funds "to pay for any abortion or to cover any part of the costs of any health plan that includes coverage of abortion." Exceptions would be made for cases of rape, incest, or danger to the life of the mother. All other abortions would be ineligible, under the Stupak-Pitts language, for:

  • direct federal funding (e.g., through Medicaid)
  • indirect federal funding in any "public option" that the legislation creates
  • subsidies or tax credits for the purpose of paying for any private plans that are sold on state "exchanges" where the uninsured who are not eligible for Medicaid and whose employers don't insure them would be required to buy health insurance

Federal funding for (non-excepted) abortions has been illegal since the Hyde Amendment to a 1976 Senate appropriations bill for the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. This amendment came just three years after the landmark Roe v. Wade decision of the U.S. Supreme Court struck down state laws prohibiting abortion.

The bill already passed by the Senate, as shepherded through by Senate Majority Leader Reid, would:

  • Require that there be a plan that covers abortion in every insurance market
  • Allow the U.S. Secretary of Health and Human Services to require coverage of any and all abortions throughout any public option program (if there is one)
  • Create new subsidies (funded via income tax credits) that will allow the uninsured to purchase, on state exchanges, private health plans that cover abortion

The Senate bill also includes language originally designed to gain the support of Senator Ben Nelson of Nebraska, a Democrat who opposes federal abortion funding. This additional language insisted that private health plans purchased on insurance exchanges must have their customers sign up separately for abortion coverage, if they desire it, provided the insurance company opts to make it available. Then the customers would have to pay the premiums for that coverage separately, by means of writing a separate check (or by separate automatic debit transactions from their bank accounts).

Abortion policies would thus have to be made available separately on the state exchanges by the insurance companies ...  if they offer abortion coverage at all. Abortion coverage would amount to a second health insurance policy that provides that one single service. Customers would buy this additional coverage, if they desire it, separately from the comprehensive health insurance packages which they also buy from the same insurance companies on a state exchange.

That provision in the Senate-passed bill would obliterate Stupak-Pitts, if the House passes the Senate bill as is. It is a provision that is loathed both by pro-choice advocates such as Planned Parenthood (it "only serves to stigmatize a woman’s right to comprehensive insurance coverage that includes abortion") and by pro-life organizations such as the U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops (“federal funds will help subsidize, and in some cases a federal agency will facilitate and promote, health plans that cover elective abortions").

The bishops' "will help subsidize" phrase alone is enough to show why the Reid-Nelson language should be scuttled and Stupak-Pitts (somehow) reinstated. Look at it this way: the federal government proposes, via a tax break, to allow subsidy dollars to remain in the right-hand pocket of needy folks so that they can buy health insurance on a state exchange. Then the feds will say, "You can buy an abortion policy, too, if you want, but you have to pay for that with dollars from your left-hand pocket."

Is there any reason why folks can't move the dollars that remain in their right-hand pocket (because they didn't have to hand them over to Uncle Sam in the form of taxes) over to their left-hand pocket and then shell out for their abortion policy from that fattened left-hand trove? Of course not.

The path to health-insurance reform through Senate reconciliation leaves Reid-Nelson in place and scuttles Stupak-Pitts instead. That needs to change before Catholics and others who favor health-insurance reform but oppose federal abortion funding can in good conscience sign on.

Though it is not a purely budgetary provision, it is not impossible that Stupak-Pitts could be inserted in the reconciliation measure/"fixer" bill, even though it technically doesn't belong there. That might need to happen if Rep. Stupak and like-minded anti-abortion Democrats are to remain in the "Yes" column when the Senate bill and its associated reconciliation measure come up for a House vote. According to  "Pro-Life Democrats Confirm: We Will Kill Health Care Bill Over Abortion Funding," an article that appeared on March 4, 2010, Stupak and at least ten other anti-abortion House Democrats are indeed likely to vote no to the Senate bill. The ten other Democrats are:

  1. Jerry Costello (IL)
  2. Kathy Dahlkemper (PA)
  3. Joe Donnelly (IN)
  4. Steve Dreihaus (OH)
  5. Brad Ellsworth (IN)
  6. Marcy Kaptur (OH)
  7. Dale Kildee (MI)
  8. Dan Lipinski (IL)
  9. Jim Oberstar (MN)
  10. Charlie Wilson (OH)

Add to those names Stupak himself and the only GOP member to vote for the original House bill, Anh "Joseph" Cao of Louisiana, who is now considered unlikely to vote yea on the Senate bill, and the 220-215 margin by which the House passed its original bill looks like it's in danger. (Keep in mind that since the House vote, four of the Democrats in the yea column have left the House of Representatives for one reason or another.)

It gets even more confusing in the Senate: under Senate rules, Republicans would have an opportunity to offer endless amendments to the reconciliation measure, which they might do just to keep the bill from ever coming to an up-or-down vote. If Stupak-Pitts is not in the reconciliation measure passed by the House (assuming the House does manage to pass such a measure) it or something like it could be offered as an amendment in the Senate ... but then the Senate parliamentarian would have to agree to let it into the reconciliation measure (or be overruled by Vice President Biden, who does not, unfortunately, have a record of opposing federal abortion funding).

Additionally, in "Democratic leaders working to win over abortion opponents for health-care reform," an article in The Washington Post of March 5, 2010, Rep. Stupak is described as disagreeing with those House leaders who insist that "rules allow only budget-related issues" to be in the Senate reconciliation measure, and that's why Stupak-Pitts must be left out. "Stupak notes that abortion changes could be added if 60 senators agreed," the article says. That is the first I have heard that a Senate supermajority of 60 has the power to bend the reconciliation rules, but if it is true, it offers yet another way to get Stupak-Pitts back into the legislation.

Then, if Stupak-Pitts (or any other amendment to the House-passed health reconciliation measure) were to pass the Senate, would it need to go through a House-Senate conference committee before the president can sign it? I'm not sure anyone has looked that far ahead yet. Stay tuned ...

Wednesday, February 24, 2010

A Catholic Case Against Abortion

Why does the Catholic Church stand against legalized abortion rights? At bottom, it's because persons cannot be — morally, legitimately, permissibly — dispensed with.

No matter how much "better" it would supposedly make things for him or her, no person's life can be rightfully discarded. Assisted suicide, euthanasia, and abortion in view of fetal abnormality: all violate this basic rule.

Again, the disposal of a human life to make things "better" for (no matter how many) others is wrong. There are times when a family may think, "Let us now tenderly pull the plug on Grandma; she's in a persistent vegetative state from which she will never recover. Meanwhile, waiting for her to die is wrecking the lives of so many of her progeny. She wouldn't want that, would she?" No, the Church says, it doesn't matter what even Grandma herself would "want." She must live until her natural death.

In all these cases the life of a person is held sacrosanct, no matter how burdensome to others or to the person himself or herself.

Any fetus, whether medically "normal" or not, is accordingly due the same respect, says the Church. It's not so much that the fetus has a "right to life." It's because the fetus is a person.

Some (including myself some time ago in this blog) have argued that a fetus isn't a person, or hasn't a soul, until there has developed it its brain the capacity for consciousness, at roughly the outset of pregnancy's third trimester. But some persons who are born brain-damaged likely never develop that capacity, and other persons such as sweet comatose Grandma may lose it prior to their death. Consciousness, though distinctly human, is not the same as personhood.

I have also argued that a pregnant woman has a unique relationship to her fetus that trumps the ordinary prohibition against discarding persons. If she in conscience determines that her fetus should not be carried to term, it's her right to abort it.

But that's wrong — for the reason, again, that "rights" are things she has, but her fetus is a person and not a thing.

This is also the (primary) reason why the Catholic Church (and most other moral human beings) will tell you that the Holocaust was wrong. Why the lynching of African Americans in the Deep South under Jim Crow was wrong. Why the indiscriminate killing of civilians in even a just war is wrong.

Now, it might be easy to conclude that the Church's proscription against dispensing with persons flows from its teachings regarding the sanctity of sex and procreation when they are engaged in by a duly married couple. It is true, of course, that the Church insists on sacramental marriage as the foundation-stone of our entire social order. The Church accordingly stands against such things as human cloning and test-tube babies because they rob even a hypothetical fetus of the accouterments of such a sacramental genesis.

Moreover, though, by turning it into an object to be prevented from existing — the reason for the Church's stance against artificial birth control — or a product that can be forced to come to be, such practices are deemed wrong on yet a second count, even when undertaken by "well-meaning" folks for seemingly justifiable reasons.

Yet a human clone or a test-tube baby is still a person. He or she didn't come about in the approved way, but never mind. The same respect is owed to him or her as to any other person. The sanctity of personhood transcends even sacramentality and sexual and social morality.

But why? Why would considerations of personhood or soul trump, in Catholic belief, even sacramentality. Perhaps it's because human personhood images that of God Himself. When we Catholics sing of "God in Three Persons, Blessed Trinity," we aren't just whistling Dixie.

Thursday, February 18, 2010

The Very Logic of Christianity

The following "My Turn" column appeared in a recent edition of The Catholic Review, the weekly newspaper of the Archdiocese of Baltimore:

Theology series aids relationships

Rob Bart Jr.


Growing up outside the Catholic Church in the ’60s, I did not have the benefit of a strong instruction on chastity. Becoming a Catholic in 1999 opened for me a new world of sacraments, saints, popes and the Mass.

A friend, Lou Breschi, shared Christopher West’s video tape series on John Paul II’s Theology of the Body (TOB) with me. My wife, Ginnie, and I watched the eight talks and saw he had written something so incredible that it needed to be shared with everyone – to heal the wounds so prevalent today in marriage and relationships. We agreed we would spend the rest of our lives learning and sharing this message which is the very logic of Christianity.

The legacy that John Paul left us is not new Catholic teaching, but a repackaging of the Gospel message “truth proposed not imposed.”

He teaches us we are not called to be more spiritual, but to be more incarnational. We are embodied souls; He put flesh on our spiritual lives. Ginnie has a great way of looking at it: “We are not like a peanut, the hull being the body and the nut being the soul – discard the hull to get to the nut. Rather, we are like sugar snap peas, it’s all good!”

Recognizing this, TOB helps us to answer two profound questions: “What does it mean to be human?” and “How do I live my life in a way to bring true happiness?”

To answer these, we consider what is the deepest yearning of every human heart. Is it to love and be loved? If so, how?

To answer these questions, John Paul takes us back to the garden, not my vegetable garden where we spend most of our free time in the summer, but “The Garden,” where Adam and Eve lived and loved in perfection, which is our true calling. We get a glimpse that they, and we, are made in the image of God and called to participate in the eternal exchange of love between Father, Son and Holy Spirit, which is self-giving divine love. We learned there is a ‘spousal meaning’ of the body. We are made in one human nature, embodied as male and female and made for union and communion through the sincere and fruitful gift of self. One of the major keys of TOB is that we are made for self-donation. Ask yourself, when are you happiest? Is it when you are giving or receiving?

John Paul proceeds to show us how the fall of man put an end to this perfection, but Christ’s redemption gives us an opportunity to live this way again. Do you yearn for more meaning, true love in your relationships, in your sexuality? Do you believe it is even possible or just a remote hope? If you were given a real way in your real everyday life to realize your heart’s deepest longing, would you accept it? Do you want it? If you do or are not sure, join us for the next study of TOB [here, the author mentions some local parishes, dates, and times].

(Rob Bart Jr. is a St. Francis Xavier parishioner in the Baltimore Archdiocese.)

I would like to add a hearty Amen! to the idea that the chastity message embodied in John Paul's teaching "is the very logic of Christianity." I once didn't understand that; now I do.

John Paul II's book The Theology of the Body: Human Love in the Divine Plan is a compendium of addresses the late pope gave on his "theology of the body" for the benefit of his "Wednesday audiences" from 1979 to 1984, early in his pontificate.

For the benefit of lay audiences, Christopher West elucidated what the Holy Father had to say in his 2004 book Theology of the Body for Beginners: A Basic Introduction to Pope John Paul II's Sexual Revolution.

Mr. West also maintains two websites (here and here) devoted to spreading the word about the theology of the body. Through the first website (click here) you can obtain various books, DVDs, etc. that can be used for private contemplation or for study groups.

Most of these materials are Catholic-oriented, but there are also items aimed at Protestants, since what is at stake is indeed "the very logic of Christianity."

Sunday, February 14, 2010

In Search of Justice

Michael J. Sandel's Justice: What's the Right Thing To Do? is a must-read for those who seek, in the systematic application of moral-philosophical argument, a rational basis for answering some of the thorniest questions surrounding us today. Among the issues Sandel brings up are "The Abortion and Stem Cell Debates," "Same-Sex Marriage," "Citizenship, Sacrifice, and Service," and "The Moral Limits of Markets." His approach will, I think, strike many readers as fresh and helpful.

Justice, the concept of moral rightness based on ethics, rationality, law, natural law, religion, fairness, and equity, is of ultimate importance to a democratic society and its politics. Sandel is a "higher-norms" liberal in a sense that went out with the assassinations of Martin Luther King and Robert F. Kennedy in the 1960s. He opposes the underpinnings of much "liberal" thought today, especially that of ultra civil libertarians who think First Amendment rights are paramount, while quarreling as well with today's right-wing libertarians and individualist, market-loving conservatives.

Sandel presents a pared down history of moral philosophy in a way that makes for anything but heavy lifting for lay readers like thee and me, so clear and crisp is his exposition. We get various strains of Western ethical thought laid before us in the context of moral dilemmas we can relate to. Due to the aptness of Sandel's examples, as we read his opening chapters we feel immediately comfortable with our comprehension of:

  • The traditional utilitarian thought of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill.
  • Today's resurgent libertarianism as embodied by economist Milton Friedman and philosopher Robert Nozick.

Utilitarianism presumes that justice is a matter of calculating which moral choices make for the greatest utility — happiness, pleasure, satisfaction, the opposite of suffering or pain — for the greatest number of people. Libertarianism, on the other hand, holds that morality is ultimately a matter of individual freedom and uncoerced consent. Sandel gives us reason to believe each of these two principles might work as a solid foundation for general social morality ... and then gives us counterexamples to convince us that both are flawed.

Even so, utilitarianism and libertarianism lie at the heart of many of our moral attitudes today. They are not wrong per se; Sandel wants us not so much to abandon them as to go beyond them.

Libertarianism and Utilitarianism

Libertarianism in particular appeals to the political right and the political left: the right adores marketplaces that leave us free to choose what to do with our own resources; the left adores, say, a woman's unfettered "right to choose."

Utilitarian thought undergirds many of the arguments today's liberals make about the welfare state, in the context of wanting to increase society's overall quotient of happiness be taking wealth from the rich to give to the poor. Conservatives, for their part, are themselves utilitarian when they point to the ability of the "invisible hand" of markets to allocate goods and services in ways that will provide the greatest economic benefit to the most people.

Sandel frames his arguments against both utilitarianism and libertarianism in terms of hot-button topics of the present. The rights and wrongs of surrogate motherhood are a case in point. A utilitarian would say that an infertile couple paying another woman to bear their child maximizes the happiness of all concerned, as the couple winds up with a child and the surrogate mother winds up with a tidy monetary reward. A libertarian, meanwhile, would say that all parties have exercised free choice in the absence of governmental or societal coercion, so what's not to like?

Well, Sandel points out, what about the notion that "surrogacy contracts degrade children and women’s labor by treating them as if they were commodities"? Or that "valuing everything according to utility (or money) degrades those goods and social practices — including children, pregnancy, and parenting — that are properly valued according to higher norms"? (These are arguments Sandel borrows from contemporary moral philosopher Elizabeth S. Anderson.) We need a theory of moral justice, Sandel says, that take account of these "higher norms" and "modes of valuation" that utilitarianism and libertarianism are blind to.

Are There Universal Human Rights?

What, then, lies beyond utilitarianism and libertarianism? Specifically, are there universal human rights that are not possible to justify in terms of either of those approaches?

"Consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slavery" can be done freely under libertarianism, Sandel notes, yet few libertarians would find either one moral. A consistent libertarian, I might add, would not object to an "assisted suicide" pact with the likes of a Dr. Kevorkian, if entered into freely. Even among libertarians, few would agree that these things are moral or just, so there must be limits to libertarianism.

As for utilitarianism, Sandel writes:

You might defend human rights on the grounds that respecting them will maximize utility in the long run. In that case, however, your reason for respecting rights is not to respect the person who holds them but to make things better for everyone. It is one thing to condemn the scenario of the suffering child because it reduces overall utility, and something else to condemn it as an intrinsic moral wrong, an injustice to the child.

If we want to reject the notion that we "own" ourselves (the libertarian mantra) even to the extent of permitting intentional self-destruction, and to hold moreover that our continued existence as individuals ought not to be subsumed to computations involving the general welfare of society (as utilitarians would hold), then how can we anchor in rational belief our intuitions of intrinsic rights that go beyond the libertarian mantra and the utilitarian bottom line? Doesn't morality, in fact, insist first and foremost that we cherish all human beings qua human beings?

Sandel, in chapter five, says a groundbreaking answer to this question was offered by 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant. Kant upped the ante on the very definition of freedom that had been assumed by proto-libertarians of his day. According to Kant, Sandel writes,

Our capacity for reason is bound up with our capacity for freedom. Taken together, these capacities make us distinctive, and set us apart from mere animal existence. They make us more than mere creatures of appetite.

These two uniquely human capacities, for reason and for freedom, are for Kant the solid foundation for a belief in universal human rights. We apply reason to the question of morality, according to Kant, and we find

 ... the moral worth of an action consists not in the consequences that flow from it, but in the intention from which the act is done. What matters [to Kant] is the motive, and the motive must be of a certain kind. What matters is doing the right thing because it’s right, not for some ulterior motive. (Sandel's words, my italics)

If we are to do the right things for the right reasons, then we must determine our moral duties independently of our personal desires. Our ability to do so (whether a person actually manages to do so in living is life is another matter) is, for Kant, that which lends human lives their dignity and respect.

We humans are accordingly subject to universal moral imperatives in Kant's view; Kant collected these moral mandates all into a single overarching principle, the "categorical imperative." Kant's categorical imperative is distinct from "hypothetical" imperatives that depend on intended outcomes. If we are just and moral, we need to yield to this categorical imperative, to set aside our individual desires. Accordingly, we must never treat persons as means to our own ends.

Kant's categorical imperative is paradoxically one that we, in our freedom, must choose. If we fail to choose it, even though pure reason bespeaks its validity, we are accordingly slaves to our own desires and not truly free!

Kant on Casual Sex

Hence, Kant objects to (among other things) today's "casual" sex:

[Kant] opposes every conceivable sexual practice except sexual intercourse between husband and wife. Whether all of Kant’s views on sex actually follow from his moral philosophy is less important than the underlying idea they reflect — that we do not own ourselves and are not at our own disposal. He objects to casual sex (by which he means sex outside of marriage), however consensual, on the grounds that it is degrading  and objectifying to both partners. Casual sex is objectionable, he thinks, because it is all about the satisfaction of sexual desire, not about respect for the humanity of one’s partner.

In short, casual, unmarried sex is out of bounds, for Kant, for the reason that we do not "own" ourselves — including our own sexuality!

From Kant's Categorical Imperative to John Rawls' Ideals of Political Justice

Kant did not specify how to turn his categorical imperative into a system of political justice. Twentieth-century philosopher John Rawls extended Kant's ideas into a theory of how a just state ought to operate.

What principles, Rawls asked, would we all agree to if we were placed in a situation of initial equality? That is, if we had no advance knowledge of what tenets of social morality would feather our own nests — of who was highborn and who was low, who was well-off and who needy, who was hale and who sickly — and if we all came together under the aegis of pure reason to produce an ideal "social contract," what ought its terms to be? Sandel:

Rawls believes that two principles of justice would emerge from the hypothetical contract. The first provides equal basic liberties for all citizens, such as freedom of speech and religion. This principle takes priority over [utilitarian] considerations of social utility and the general welfare. [Rawls'] second principle concerns social and economic equality. Although it does not require an equal distribution of income and wealth, it permits only those social and economic inequalities that work to the advantage of the least well off members of society.

If we are each just as likely to be poor as to be rich, sick as to be well, obtuse as to be smart, then by Rawls' second principle we would insist on social policies that work to the advantage of the former, weaker categories, rather than the latter, stronger ones. Any other allocation of society's "goods," tangible and intangible, would allow the better endowed to trample the worse off in their reach for ever greater wealth.

Accordingly, in Rawls' view we must start our deliberations about moral justice from behind an imaginary "veil of ignorance," not knowing in advance who would be dealt the most desirable hands in life. If we did so, clearly we would severally subject ourselves to binding obligations that would go beyond individual "consent" as customarily upheld by libertarians: contracts in which "you scratch my back and I'll scratch yours."

In addition to such overt contracts of mutual benefit, in Rawls' philosophy there might be implicit contracts in such a society that we do not overtly consent to. For example, if we allow a "squeegee man" at a traffic light to wash our windshield, we would be implicitly bound to tip him, prior agreement or no.

Meanwhile, certain actual contracts that people enter into might be morally invalid — e.g., when one person uses superior knowledge to inveigle another person into a disadvantageous agreement. Banks that sold subprime mortgages to house buyers that hadn't a prayer of paying them back, and then bundled the bad mortgages into marketable securities to augment their own profitability, come to mind here.

To Rawls, a ideal society would serve the interests, first and foremost, of those born without natural gifts and advantages in life: caring parents, stable homes, good schools, etc. Though economic inequalities would still exist, "only those social and economic inequalities ... that work to the benefit of the least advantaged members of society" would be allowed. That's why doctors, for instance, would be seen to deserve higher pay than bus drivers.

This is not socialism. Strict equality of income and wealth would not be enforced. Even so, says Sandel, Rawls' "theory of justice ... represents the most compelling case for a more equal society that American political philosophy has yet produced."

Sandel's (and Aristotle's) Third Way

Still and all, the moral philosophy of Kant as elaborated into political theory by John Rawls is basically a quasi-utilitarian amplification of the libertarian idea of freedom. It does not always match Sandel's preferred way of determining what's just:

A third approach says that justice means giving people what they morally deserve — allocating goods to reward and promote virtue. As we will see when we turn to Aristotle ... the virtue-based approach connects justice to reflection about the good life.

In other words, though Rawls' theory of justice is pretty good, there needs to be more to the politics of social justice. There is, for instance, the question of actively promoting virtue by having our civic institutions —including our national government — be non-neutral (gasp!) as to what constitutes "the good life."

Our society has today become one that is carefully neutral about the proper grounds of justice and social morality. Anything other than neutrality about where the roots of morality lie, we fear, risks promoting intolerance, whether religious or of other kinds. Accordingly our governments, at all levels, bend over backwards to avoid taking stands on important moral questions.

Sandel does not dwell long on the notion of religion as the viable substrate of morality, it must be noted. While reading his book, however, I could not help thinking of our society's strict-neutrality policy as a way by which it avoids taking any sort of stand in favor of religion qua religion.

Debating Affirmative Action

Our society's "liberals" are typically the most adamant about the strict-neutrality policy. Yet Sandel shows that some of the pet goals that liberals seek, including affirmative action in college admissions, are hard to justify without accepting that "justice in allocating access to a university has something to do with the goods that universities properly pursue."

What "goods" should universities properly pursue, then? That is a question that depends on the university's telos: Aristotle's word for the appropriate ends or purposes toward which a thing (such as a university) is intrinsically directed.

A college or university is intrinsically aimed, among other things, toward serving the common good through teaching and research. But when is a university "serving the common good"? Answering that question demands that we come to some agreement as to what "the common good" is.

To do that, we cannot at one and the same time insist on having our civic institutions be fastidiously neutral among warring religious or secular worldviews. We need to be able to choose among "competing notions of the virtues [which an] institution should honor and reward." If we want to promote civic ideals such as the ability of various races and ethnicities to join in this nation's common enterprise, then our colleges and universities must follow through on their telos. They must not shy away from promulgating a non-neutral conception of "virtue."

"Justice is teleological," writes Sandel. "Defining rights requires us to figure out the telos (the purpose, end, or essential nature) of the social practice in question." Who has what rights to admission to Harvard depends on Harvard's purpose/end/essential nature as a university.

"Closely connected to the debate about a university’s purpose," Sandel continues,

is a question about honor: What virtues or excellences do universities properly honor and reward? Those who believe that universities exist to celebrate and reward scholarly excellence alone are likely to reject affirmative action, whereas those who believe universities also exist to promote certain civic ideals may well embrace it.

The question at hand is, then, should our universities and public institutions curry a civic virtue such as mutual respect and tolerance by going out of their to remedy historical injustices against African Americans and other groups — even to the extent of overlooking the lower test scores of black applicants vis-à-vis whites? The answer to that question depends on what politics is for.

The Telos of Politics

A deeper question is, accordingly, can we come together and reason our way toward a telos-honoring answer to the first question? That deeper question concerns the telos of politics itself.

We today hesitate to invest our politics with a determinate telos that "would seem to preempt the right of citizens to decide for themselves," per whatever whims of public opinion are rife at the time, what they want their political system to do. If our primary concern is to use politics and government to maximize individual freedom, and nothing else, we will accordingly set aside Aristotle's ideas about the "purpose of politics." For Aristotle held that politics is not really intended "to set up a framework of rights that is neutral among ends. It is [rather] to form good citizens and to cultivate good character."

Those who deserve the most honor in a society, Aristotle taught, are "those who excel in civic virtue, those who are best at deliberating about the common good." Accordingly, the telos of a university is to produce graduates who are, first and foremost, excellent at deliberating about the common good — and that fact requires colleges to use admissions policies that are broadly inclusive and do not overemphasize purely academic credentials.

If so, though, doesn't such a commitment run smack against our widely accepted idea that we all all "free and independent selves, unbound by moral ties we haven’t chosen"? Concerning affirmative action in particular, if we ourselves never enslaved, or discriminated against, African Americans, then why do our institutions owe African Americans anything in the way of affirmative action, apologies, or reparations?

Sandel uses this example of a policy dear to the hearts of political liberals today to show that the strict neutrality which those same liberals cherish with respect to competing systems of moral thought and religious belief (or unbelief) won't wash. In order to nail down an irrefutable defense of affirmative action, liberals must show how affirmative action programs lend themselves to a particular view of the basis for the "good life."

Moral Individualism vs. Obligations of Solidarity

Sandel shows that liberals' chariness of rooting affirmative action in a particular conception of the good furthers, in an inadvertent way, an ethical approach more typical of today's political conservatives, for it is the one that (among other shortcomings) denies any societal obligation to provide affirmative action for disadvantaged minorities. He calls this approach "moral individualism." According to it:

... to be free is to be subject only to obligations I voluntarily incur; whatever I owe others, I owe by virtue of some act of consent — a choice or a promise or an agreement I have made, be it tacit or explicit.

Moral individualism, Sandel says, is blind to Aristotle's telos of politics: to form good citizens and to cultivate good character. It is also blind to the ways that we are, all of us, morally "encumbered" by the specific histories of the communities of which we are a part: our families, our schools, our religious institutions, our ethnic groups, our unions, our military services, our professional associations, our localities, our states, our nations.

We are all, says Sandel, members of an interlocking network of clans, tribes, associations, and institutions, whose specific stories stamp us with moral imperatives beyond those that pure reason can show to be universal, and beside those obligations we take on voluntarily in ways that moral individualists would uphold.

In this regard, Sandel embraces the ideas of ethicist Alasdair MacIntyre, who writes:

... the young German who believes that being born after 1945 means that what Nazis did to Jews has no moral relevance to his relationship to his Jewish contemporaries.

To which Sandel adds:

MacIntyre sees in [such a] stance a moral shallowness. It wrongly assumes that "the self is detachable from its social and historical roles and statuses."

If our individual selves are non-detachable from our collective pasts, then our historical narratives obligate us. The story of what Germans did to Jews during World War II binds today's Germans to an exquisiteness of sensitivity to never repeating the anti-Semitic past — a past in which it became illegal, under Nazi rule, for Germans to deliberate together openly about the common good.

Americans, for their part, have their own historical narratives that obligate them to offer affirmative action to African Americans ... in order to fully integrate them into the circle of those who excel at deliberating about the common good.

Moral imperatives like these are what Sandel calls the "obligations of solidarity." They sometimes require us to do what we might not like doing, such as (if we are white) ceding spots in the freshman class at Harvard to African Americans with lower test scores. But they also obligate us to do things that we enjoy doing, such as demonstrating our patriotism by rising for our national anthem. Obligations of solidarity are a two-edged sword.

Storytelling Beings

It is the stories of our lives that create our specific obligations of solidarity. We are "storytelling beings," says Sandel with MacIntyre.

Our personal stories differ from one individual to the next. Yet they overlap in terms of our joint membership in clans and tribes that we are born, or move, into.

None of us can make sense of our individual moral and ethical obligations, Sandel says, unless we see how they flow, some of them, from the narrative histories that shape us and take us past the obligations of individual consent that libertarians look to ... and also beyond the "natural, universal duties" that, Kant showed, do not require our consent at all.

The moral duties that our narrative histories impose on us are particular, not universal. People belonging to tribes with other narrative histories are not bound by the same claims of community. We Americans have a duty to salute the Stars and Stripes, while a Frenchman is obligated to salute the Tricolor.

An American is born into one tribe, a German into another. Still, the story of an American Catholic, which is what I am, intersects the story of a German Catholic, which is what Pope Benedict XVI is. The Pope's personal story and my own personal story have in common that we are both Catholics and are therefore both obliged to uphold Catholic beliefs and teachings, unless in good conscience we cannot.

The moral duties that our narrative histories impose on us form, then, intersecting "obligations of solidarity." As such, they don't live and die by our signing on to them voluntarily. We are encumbered by them beyond our intentional consent, and beyond Kant's categorical imperative to do no injustice to any fellow human.

Linking Our Narrative Histories with the Philosophies of Aristotle, Kant, and Rawls

We have obligations of solidarity that the stories of our communal lives impose on us. How does this source of human moral obligation tie into the telos of our political system?

In his chapter on "What Do We Owe One Another?/Dilemmas of Loyalty," Sandel suggests that it is right and proper for leaders of latter-day Germany to have apologized to Jews for the Holocaust, and to have paid "billions of dollars in reparations ... in the form of payments to individual survivors and to the state of Israel." Why so?

The main justifications for public apologies [and for reparations] are to honor the memory of those who have suffered injustice at the hands (or in the name) of the political community, to recognize the persisting effects of injustice on victims and their descendants, and to atone for the wrongs committed by those who inflicted the injustice or failed to prevent it.

Key words here are "injustice ... in the name of the political community." "Injustice" takes us back to Kantian notions of the categorical imperative: universal truths of morality absolutely prohibit doing what Germany under the Nazis did to the Jews of Europe. "In the name of the political community" joins Aristotle with Rawls, and unites both of them with Alasdair MacIntyre, the exponent of the idea that our joint communal histories saddle us with obligations of solidarity.

A circle formed by the moral philosophies of Aristotle, Kant, Rawls, and MacIntyre thereby tells us that utilitarianism, libertarianism, and "moral individualism" are not enough, and that repairing "injustice ... in the name of the political community" can call forth from us a morality of higher norms.

Tuesday, January 26, 2010

"Rise in teenage pregnancy rate spurs new debate"

The epigraph to this rededicated blog has been changed. It is now a quote from Mere Christianity by C.S. Lewis:

Chastity is the most unpopular of the Christian virtues. There is no getting away from it; the Christian rule is, "Either marriage, with complete faithfulness to your partner, or else total abstinence."

"Rise in teenage pregnancy rate spurs new debate on arresting it," an article from today's The Washington Post, plays off Lewis's sentiment about chastity and abstinence in ways that the greatest explainer of Christian belief of the 20th century could not have anticipated. Lewis died in 1963 before the "sexual revolution" had entrenched itself in the culture. Mere Christianity was the outgrowth of BBC radio talks made between 1941 and 1944, while Lewis, a Britisher, was an academic at Oxford during World War II.

Now, less than half a century later,

The abortion rate among teenagers rose 1 percent in 2006 from the previous year — to 19.3 abortions per 1,000 women in that age group, the analysis [of the most recent data collected by the federal government and the nation's leading reproductive-health think tank] found. Taking that and miscarriages into account, the analysis showed that the pregnancy rate among U.S. women younger than 20 in 2006 was 71.5 per 1,000 women, a 3 percent increase from the rate of 69.5 in 2005. That translated into 743,000 pregnancies among teenagers, or about 7 percent of women in this age group.
has become a news item to be consumed with the morning cereal. In Lewis's time there was not such frank talk about adults', much less teenagers', sex lives.

In the year Lewis died, 1963, although teen pregnancies and teen births were already high in the U.S. by the historical standards of the time, the culture had not yet begun to rely heavily on sex education in the public schools to rein in teen sexual expression. I was a (male) teenager of 16 in that year. The persons we now speak of as "women under age 20" were, at the time, still "girls." The rule was, "Nice girls don't."

In those now seemingly halcyon days, I never had a "sex ed" course, though I believe girls were getting some preliminary form of it in junior high school gym classes under the topic of "hygiene." I wound up in private school by 9th grade, so maybe I just missed it.

Today, those who say sex-ed courses should teach the use of condoms and other birth control methods duke it out with those who want an "abstinence only" curriculum.

I would recommend "chastity only," not "abstinence only." Abstinence per se is not a virtue; chastity is. Abstinence is a negative; chastity is a positive.

The purpose of a public school education is to instill in children the virtues they need to possess if they are going to be good citizens. Not just some of the virtues, all of them. And chastity is one of them.

C.S. Lewis continued, in his essay on chastity:

I want to make it as clear as I possibly can that the centre of Christian morality is not here. If anyone thinks that Christians regard unchastity as the supreme vice, he is quite wrong. The sins of the flesh are bad, but they are the least bad of all sins. All the worst pleasures are purely spiritual: the pleasure of putting other people in the wrong, of bossing and patronising and spoiling sport, and back-biting, the pleasures of power, of hatred. For there are two things inside me, competing with the human self which I must try to become. They are the Animal self, and the Diabolical self. The Diabolical self is the worse of the two. That is why a cold, self-righteous prig who goes regularly to church may be far nearer to hell than a prostitute. But, of course, it is better to be neither.

I think Lewis (pictured at right) was right about one thing here, but wrong about another. He was right to suggest that the Diabolical self can turn us into self-righteous prigs, or as Jesus put it in one of the Gospels, Matthew 23:27, into "whitewashed tombs ... full of dead men's bones and everything unclean." In other words, the worst kind of hypocrites.

But Lewis was wrong to suggest that "the pleasure of putting other people in the wrong, of bossing and patronising and spoiling sport, and back-biting, the pleasures of power, of hatred" are in a different category than the pleasures of the flesh. We have seen, in the years since Lewis wrote, the opening up of the culture to unfettered sexuality. We have also seen a huge rise in all of the ostensibly non-sexual offenses Lewis mentions above.

Think about Internet "flame wars." Think about vitriolic talk radio. Think about all the current furor over the "culture of power in Washington D.C." Think about the naked hatred that seems to be fueling much of our politics today. They suggest that maybe, just maybe, a lack of sexual chastity in the culture morphs inevitably into a lack of chastity in general.

In fact, I think that is exactly what recent history proves. If I'm right, then we all need to reclaim the notion that chastity, sexual and otherwise, lies at the very core of Judeo-Christian belief and practice.

If the monotheistic religions of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam teach the fundamental sanctity of nuptial sex — and all do — then we need to listen to them again. We need to bring their conceptions of virtue back into currency in the "public square." We need to make them once again the foundation-stones of our civic virtue.


* * *



Since the above was posted, Study: Abstinence sex-ed works appeared on the front page of The Washington Post. A scientific study published in the Archives of Pediatric & Adolescent Medicine has shown that abstinence-only sex education programs for sixth and seventh graders can result in fewer children becoming sexually active in the ensuing two years.

As a Catholic, I see that as the cup being half full. On the one hand, it counters the assertions that have recently held sway to the effect that abstinence education is a big flop. On the other hand, it apparently says nothing about abstinence-only programs that "take a moralistic tone, as many abstinence programs do. Most notably, the sessions [under study] encouraged children to delay sex until they are ready, not necessarily until married; did not portray sex outside marriage as never appropriate; and did not disparage condoms.

Would "moralistic" abstinence programs that advocate delaying sex until marriage, not having sex outside marriage at all, and not using artificial means of birth control fare as well? Or perhaps even better? Those important questions are beyond the scope of the study ...

Sunday, January 24, 2010

Rededicating This Blog Yet Again!

An occasional topic of this blog has been Christian chastity. In this blog and in my personal commitments, I've been wobbly about chastity in the past, in terms of what it means, of how important it is (or isn't) to the Christian. Of late I've come to realize that chastity lies at the core of Christian belief and practice.

Sexual chastity, in particular. There are all sorts of promiscuity, and all sorts of its opposite, chastity. But the word chastity calls to mind, mainly, sexual restraint.

Ever since I've been a Christian at all, and it's been some 30 years since I was baptized, I've not been particularly chaste. Nor have I been particularly promiscuous. I've been somewhere in between, and I've rationalized it by imagining that questions of chastity and promiscuity are peripheral to being a good Christian in this day and age.

Wrong.

It's just that, today, in this modern world, traditional Christian beliefs about such things as the sanctity of married, one-man-one-woman, sexually exclusive fidelity have become so much more "radical" than they ever were before that I wanted to believe that some kind of a new dispensation had arrived from God. We could be good, holy, loving-of-others Christians while setting aside the old rules about sex.

I've reformed my views. Why? Because I finally came to see that I've harbored those old views all my life, while at the same time not admitting to others, or myself, that I did.

It's easy to juggle internal contradictions like that — until such time as you realize you've been doing so. I've always absolutely adored the idea of a man and a woman finding one another, pairing off for life under the auspices of holy wedlock, coming to each other as virgins on their wedding night, cherishing each other for the rest of time (and beyond). It's even better when their union produces abundant children whom they love, and who love them back. And so it goes, from generation to generation.

Except, today, it doesn't work that way. Not all the time.

Still, it happens often enough (well, maybe not the virgins-on-their-wedding-night part) that the ancient pattern is not lost to view. Yet the deviations from the pattern are so ubiquitous today that they seem "normal" and the pattern itself seems "outdated" and "quaint."

That's one reason why I say that belief in the sanctity of the pattern is "radical." Another reason has to do with the root meaning of "radical," which is, of course, "of or pertaining to the root." For I have finally put it together in my mind that the old ideas about sexual chastity and holiness lie at the root of Judeo-Christian beliefs.

If you go back to the Hebrew Bible — Christians call it the Old Testament — you find just about every story laced with allusions to sex and marriage. In Genesis alone: Adam and Eve; Abraham and Sarah; Jacob and Rachel (pictured at left), and so on. Even on the Ark "two of every sort [of animal]...male and female" are Noah's passengers.

In the New Testament we learn that Jesus was born of Mary after God's angel visited her and told her that she, though a virgin, would conceive by the Holy Spirit.

Why all the marital imagery?

Catholic theology holds that in the One God in Three Persons — in the Most Holy Trinity, Father, Son, and Holy Spirit — the Persons are related in a way that human marriage and procreation reflect. From the love between the Father and His only-begotten Son proceeds the Holy Spirit. Though this divine love is not sexual, human sexual love and procreation mirror it.

If this is so, then our chastity is favored by the very weave of the fabric of reality. God wove reality in a way that makes wrong the sorts of promiscuity we claim the "right" to freely embrace today.

If we don't like the "weave of reality" metaphor, we can put it differently: Reality is so deeply colored by God's insistence on chastity that it might as well have been dyed that way ... and, shucks, I guess we're back to the metaphor of reality as a fabric that God has woven and given indelible color to.

Another try: God in effect "tattoos" reality with a mark of His holiness, but we are blind to it unless we use sex aright.

But why? It seems more logical that the prevailing wisdom today — that we are "free" to have sex of any type we want, with whatever consenting adults we choose — would be correct. Why would sexual license be responsible for so much of the world's pain?

Don't believe me? Just watch The Maury Povich Show when "Who's My Baby's Daddy?" is its theme, as it so frequently is.

Or, think about the approximately 46 million abortions that are performed worldwide every year. According to this page, 1.21 million induced abortions were performed in the United States in 2005, down from 1.31 million in 2000. From 1973 through 2005, more than 45 million legal abortions occurred in the U.S. Each abortion, wherever it occurs, is a tragedy. Even abortion doctors admit that their patients are anything but blithe as they enter and, after the procedure, leave the clinic.

That observation alone does not make abortions, though deemed legal and permissible by modern society, morally wrong. But it tells me that the general social situation of which the high incidence of abortion is but a symptom represents a veritable cultural sickness. Purposely killing the baby in your own womb is something that should happen rarely if ever. Yet it is anything but rare.

Again, why? Why is the current sexual permissiveness so hard on us? If sex is natural and normal in great variety and quantity, as we are told today, why does it so often put us in situations of regret?

My answer is that permissiveness goes against the grain of reality. No wonder it gives us so many splinters.

And that, to me, bespeaks the existence of God. Why would there be an anti-permissive grain to reality at all, unless that reality reflects at its deepest level something about the inner nature of the God who fashioned it?